User:Hogo-2020/sandbox

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Social justice

Social justice is the relation of balance between individuals and society measured by comparing distribution of wealth differences, from personal liberties to fair privilege opportunities. In Western as well as in older Asian cultures, the concept of social justice has often referred to the process of ensuring that individuals fulfill their societal roles and receive what was their due from society.[1][2][3] In the current global grassroots movements for social justice, the emphasis has been on the breaking of barriers for social mobility, the creation of safety nets and economic justice.[4][5][6][7][8] Social justice assigns rights and duties in the institutions of society, which enables people to receive the basic benefits and burdens of cooperation. The relevant institutions often include taxation, social insurance, public health, public school, public services, labor law and regulation of markets, to ensure fair distribution of wealth, and equal opportunity.[9]

Interpretations that relate justice to a reciprocal relationship to society are mediated by differences in cultural traditions, some of which emphasize the individual responsibility toward society and others the equilibrium between access to power and its responsible use.[10] Hence, social justice is invoked today while reinterpreting historical figures such as Bartolomé de las Casas, in philosophical debates about differences among human beings, in efforts for gender, ethnic, and social equality, for advocating justice for migrants, prisoners, the environment, and the physically and developmentally disabled.[11][12][13]

While concepts of social justice can be found in classical and Christian philosophical sources, from Plato and Aristotle to Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas, the term “social justice” finds its earliest uses in the late 18th century—albeit with unclear theoretical or practical meanings.[14][15][16] Thus the use of the term was early on subject to accusations of redundancy—are not all claims of justice “social”? – and of rhetorical flourish, perhaps, but not necessarily, related to amplifying one view of distributive justice. In the coining and definition of the term in the natural law social scientific treatise of Luigi Taparelli, SJ, in the early 1840’s,[17] Taparelli established the natural law principle that corresponded to the evangelical principle of brotherly love—i.e. social justice reflects After the Revolutions of 1848 the term was popularized generically through the writings of Antonio Rosmini-Serbati.[18][19]

In the late industrial revolution, progressive American legal scholars began to use the term more, particularly Louis Brandeis and Roscoe Pound From the early 20th century it was also embedded in international law and institutions; the preamble to establish the International Labour Organization recalled that "universal and lasting peace can be established only if it is based upon social justice." In the later 20th century, social justice was made central to the philosophy of the social contract, primarily by John Rawls in A Theory of Justice (1971). In 1993, the Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action treats social justice as a purpose of human rights education.[20][21]

History[edit]

Main articles: Social contract, Justice, Corrective justice, and Distributive justice

The different concepts of justice, as discussed in ancient Western philosophy, were typically centered upon the community.

An artist's rendering of what Plato might have looked like. From Raphael's early 16th century painting Scuola di Atene.
  • Plato wrote in The Republic that it would be an ideal state that "every member of the community must be assigned to the class for which he finds himself best fitted." [22] In an article for J.N.V University, author D.R. Bhandari says, "Justice is, for Plato, at once a part of human virtue and the bond, which joins man together in society. It is the identical quality that makes good and social. Justice is an order and duty of the parts of the soul, it is to the soul as health is to the body. Plato says that justice is not mere strength, but it is a harmonious strength. Justice is not the right of the stronger but the effective harmony of the whole. All moral conceptions revolve about the good of the whole-individual as well as social".[23]
  • Plato believed rights existed only between free people, and the law should take "account in the first instance of relations of inequality in which individuals are treated in proportion to their worth and only secondarily of relations of equality." Reflecting this time when slavery and subjugation of women was typical, ancient views of justice tended to reflect the rigid class systems that still prevailed. On the other hand, for the privileged groups, strong concepts of fairness and the community existed. Distributive justice was said by Aristotle to require that people were distributed goods and assets according to their merit.[24]
  • Socrates (through Plato's dialogue Crito) is credited with developing the idea of a social contract, whereby people
    Roman copy in marble of a Greek bronze bust of Aristotle by Lysippos, c. 330 BC. The alabaster mantle is modern.
    ought to follow the rules of a society, and accept its burdens because they have accepted its benefits.[25] During the Middle Ages, religious scholars particularly, such as Thomas Aquinas continued discussion of justice in various ways, but ultimately connected being a good citizen to the purpose of serving God.
  • After the Renaissance and Reformation, the modern concept of social justice, as developing human potential, began to emerge through the work of a series of authors. Baruch Spinoza in On the Improvement of the Understanding (1677) contended that the one true aim of life should be to acquire "a human character much more stable than [one's] own", and to achieve this "pitch of perfection...The chief good is that he should arrive, together with other individuals if possible, at the possession of the aforesaid character." During the enlightenment and responding to the French and American Revolutions, Thomas Paine similarly wrote in The Rights of Man (1792) society should give "genius a fair and universal chance" and so "the construction of government ought to be such as to bring forward...all that extent of capacity which never fails to appear in revolutions."[26]

Although there is no certainty about the first use of the term "social justice", early

Socrates

sources can be found in Europe in the 18th century[27] Some references to the use of the expression are in articles of journals aligned with the spirit of the Enlightenment, in which social justice is described as an obligation of the monarch;[28][29]also the term is present in books written by Catholic Italian theologians, notably members of the Society of Jesus.[30] Thus, according to this sources and the context, social justice was another term for "the justice of society", the justice that rules the relations among individuals in society, without any mention to socio-economic equity or human dignity.[31]

The usage of the term started to become more frequent by Catholic thinkers from the 1840s, beginning with the Jesuit Luigi Taparelli in Civiltà Cattolica, and based on the work of St. Thomas Aquinas. Taparelli argued that rival capitalist and socialist theories, based on subjective Cartesian thinking,undermined the unity of society present in Thomistic metaphysics as neither were sufficiently concerned with ethics. Writing in 1861, the influential British philosopher and economist, John Stuart Mill stated in Utilitarianism his view that "Society should treat all equally well who have deserved equally well of it, that is, who have deserved equally well absolutely. This is the highest abstract standard of social and distributive justice; towards which all institutions, and the efforts of all virtuous citizens, should be made in the utmost degree to converge.

Social justice has been traditionally credited to be coined by Jesuit priest Luigi Taparelli in the 1840s, but the expression is older

In the later 19th and early 20th century, social justice became an important theme in American political and legal philosophy, particularly in the work of John Dewey, Roscoe Pound and Louis Brandeis. One of the prime concerns was the Lochner era decisions of the US Supreme Court to strike down legislation passed by state governments and the Federal government for social and economic improvement, such as the eight-hour day or the right to join a trade union. After the First World War, the founding document of the International Labour Organization took up the same terminology in its preamble, stating that "peace can be established only if it is based on social justice" . From this point, the discussion of social justice entered into mainstream legal and academic discourse.

In 1931, the Pope Pius XI explicitly referred to the expression, along with the concept of subsidiarity, for the first time in Catholic social teaching in the encyclical Quadragesimo anno. Then again in Divini Redemptoris, the church pointed out that the realization of social justice relied on the promotion of the dignity of human person The same year, and because of the documented influence of Divini Redemptoris in its drafters, he Constitution of Ireland was the first one to establish the term as a principle of the economy in the State, The Constitution of Ireland was the first one to establish the term as a principle of the economy in the State, and then other countries around the world did the same throughout the 20th century, even in socialist regimes such as the Cuban Constitution in 1976.

In the late 20th century, several liberal and conservative thinkers, notably Friedrich Hayek rejected the concept by stating that it did not mean anything, or meant too many things. However the concept remained highly influential, particularly with its promotion by philosophers such as John Rawls. Even though the meaning of social justice varies, at least three common elements can be identified in the contemporary theories about it: a duty of the State to distribute certain vital means (such as economic, social, and cultural rights), the protection of human dignity, and affirmative actions to promote equal opportunities for everybody.[32]

Contemporary theory[edit]

Philosophical perspectives

Cosmic values

Hunter Lewis' work promoting natural healthcare and sustainable economies advocates for conservation as a key premise in social justice. His manifesto on sustainability ties the continued thriving of human life to real conditions, the environment supporting that life, and associates injustice with the detrimental effects of unintended consequences of human actions. Quoting classical Greek thinkers like Epicurus on the good of pursuing happiness, Hunter also cites ornithologist, naturalist, and philosopher Alexander Skutch in his book Moral Foundations:

The common feature which unites the activities most consistently forbidden by the moral codes of civilized peoples is that by their very nature they cannot be both habitual and enduring, because they tend to destroy the conditions which make them possible.

Pope Benedict XVI cites Teilhard de Chardin in a vision of the cosmos as a 'living host[33]embracing an understanding of ecology that includes humanity's relationship to others, that pollution affects not just the natural world but interpersonal relations as well. Cosmic harmony, justice and peace are closely interrelated:

If you want to cultivate peace, protect creation.[34]

In The Quest for Cosmic Justice, Thomas Sowell writes that seeking utopia, while admirable, may have disastrous effects if done without strong consideration of the economic underpinnings that support contemporary society.[35]

John Rawls

Main article: John Rawls

Political philosopher John Rawls draws on the utilitarian insights of Bentham and Mill, the social contract ideas of John Locke, and the categorical imperative ideas of Kant. His first statement of principle was made in A Theory of Justice where he proposed that, For this reason justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others.[36] A deontological proposition that echoes Kant in framing the moral good of justice in absolutist terms. His views are definitively restated in Political Liberalism where society is seen "as a fair system of co-operation over time, from one generation to the next".[37]

All societies have a basic structure of social, economic, and political institutions, both formal and informal. In testing how well these elements fit and work together, Rawls based a key test of legitimacy on the theories of social contract. To determine whether any particular system of collectively enforced social arrangements is legitimate, he argued that one must look for agreement by the people who are subject to it, but not necessarily to an objective notion of justice based on coherent ideological grounding. Obviously, not every citizen can be asked to participate in a poll to determine his or her consent to every proposal in which some degree of coercion is involved, so one has to assume that all citizens are reasonable. Rawls constructed an argument for a two-stage process to determine a citizen's hypothetical agreement:

  • The citizen agrees to be represented by X for certain purposes, and, to that extent, X holds these powers as a trustee for the citizen.
  • X agrees that enforcement in a particular social context is legitimate. The citizen, therefore, is bound by this decision because it is the function of the trustee to represent the citizen in this way.

This applies to one person who represents a small group (e.g., the organizer of a social event setting a dress code) as equally as it does to national governments, which are ultimate trustees, holding representative powers for the benefit of all citizens within their territorial boundaries.

Governments that fail to provide for welfare of their citizens according to the principles of justice are not legitimate. Governments that fail to provide for welfare of their citizens according to the principles of justice are not legitimate. To emphasize the general principle that justice should rise from the people and not be dictated by the law-making powers of governments, Rawls asserted that, "There is ... a general presumption against imposing legal and other restrictions on conduct without sufficient reason. But this presumption creates no special priority for any particular liberty." [38]This is support for an unranked set of liberties that reasonable citizens in all states should respect and uphold — to some extent, the list proposed by Rawls matches the normative human rights that have international recognition and direct enforcement in some nation states where the citizens need encouragement to act in a way that fixes a greater degree of equality of outcome. According to Rawls, the basic liberties that every good society should guarantee are:

  • Freedom of thought;
  • Liberty of conscience as it affects social relationships on the grounds of religion, philosophy, and morality;
  • Political liberties (e.g., representative democratic institutions, freedom of speech and the press, and freedom of assembly);
  • Freedom of association;
  • Freedoms necessary for the liberty and integrity of the person (namely: freedom from slavery, freedom of movement and a reasonable degree of freedom to choose one's occupation); and
  • Rights and liberties covered by the rule of law.

Thomas Pogge

Thomas Pogge's arguments pertain to a standard of social justice that creates human rights deficits.

He assigns responsibility to those who actively cooperate in designing or imposing the social institution,

that the order is foreseeable as harming the global poor and is reasonably avoidable. Pogge argues that social institutions have a negative duty to not harm the poor.[39][40]

Pogge speaks of "institutional cosmopolitanism" and assigns responsibility to institutional schemes for deficits of human rights. An example given is slavery and third parties. A third party should not recognize or enforce slavery. The institutional order should be held responsible only for deprivations of human rights that it establishes or authorizes. The current institutional design, he says, systematically harms developing economies by enabling corporate tax evasion,[41] illicit financial flows, corruption, trafficking of people and weapons. . Joshua Cohen disputes his claims based on the fact that some poor countries have done well with the current institutional design.[42]Elizabeth Kahn argues that some of these responsibilities[vague] should apply globally.

United Nations

The United Nations calls social justice "an underlying principle for peaceful and prosperous coexistence within and among nations. [43]

The United Nations' 2006 document Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations, ates that "Social justice may be broadly understood as the fair and compassionate distribution of the fruits of economic growth[44] The term "social justice" was seen by the U.N. "as a substitute for the protection of human rights [and] first appeared in United Nations texts during the second half of the 1960s. At the initiative of the Soviet Union, and with the support of developing countries, the term was used in the Declaration on Social Progress and Development, adopted in 1969."[45]

The same document reports, "From the comprehensive global perspective shaped by the United Nations Charter and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, neglect of the pursuit of social justice in all its dimensions translates into de facto acceptance of a future marred by violence, repression and chaos." [46] The report concludes, "Social justice is not possible without strong and coherent redistributive policies conceived and implemented by public agencies."[47]

The same UN document offers a concise history: e notion of social justice is relatively new. None of history’s great philosophers—not Plato or Aristotle, or Confucius or Averroes, or even Rousseau or Kant—saw the need to consider justice or the redress of injustices from a social perspective. The concept first surfaced in Western thought and political language in the wake of the industrial revolution and the parallel development of the socialist doctrine. It emerged as an expression of protest against what was perceived as the capitalist exploitation of labour and as a focal point for the development of measures to improve the human condition. It was born as a revolutionary slogan embodying the ideals of progress and fraternity. Following the revolutions that shook Europe in the mid-1800s, social justice became a rallying cry for progressive thinkers and political activists.... By the mid-twentieth century, the concept of social justice had become central to the ideologies and programmes of virtually all the leftist and centrist political parties around the world.[48]

Another key area of human rights and social justice is the United Nations's defense of children rights worldwide. In 1989, the Convention on the Rights of the Child was adopted and available for signature, ratification and accession by General Assembly resolution 44/25.[49] According to OHCHR, this convention entered into force on 2 September 1990. This convention upholds that all states have the obligation to "protect the child from all forms of physical or mental violence, injury or abuse, neglect or negligent treatment, maltreatment or exploitation, including sexual abuse."[50]

Religious perspectives[edit]

Christianity

Evangelicalism

Time magazine noted that younger Evangelicals also increasingly engage in social justice.[51] John Stott traced the call for social justice back to the cross, "The cross is a revelation of God's justice as well as of his love. That is why the community of the cross should concern itself with social justice as well as with loving philanthropy."[52]

Methodism

From its founding, Methodism was a Christian social justice movement. Under John Wesley's direction, Methodists became leaders in many social justice issues of the day, including the prison reform and abolition movements. Wesley himself was among the first to preach for slaves rights attracting significant opposition. [53][54][55]Today, social justice plays a major role in the United Methodist Church and the Free Methodist Church.[56] The Book of Discipline of the United Methodist Church says, "We hold governments responsible for the protection of the rights of the people to free and fair elections and to the freedoms of speech, religion, assembly, communications media, and petition for redress of grievances without fear of reprisal; to the right to privacy; and to the guarantee of the rights to adequate food, clothing, shelter, education, and health care.[57] The United Methodist Church also teaches population control as part of its doctrine.[58] The poor have the most urgent moral claim on the conscience of the nation.

Catholicism

Main article: Catholic social teaching

Catholic social teaching consists of those aspects of Roman Catholic doctrine which relate to matters dealing with the respect of the individual human life. A distinctive feature of Catholic social doctrine is its concern for the poorest and most vulnerable members of society. Two of the seven key areas[59] of "Catholic social teaching" are pertinent to social justice:

  • Life and dignity of the human person: The foundational principle of all Catholic social teaching is the sanctity of all human life and the inherent dignity of every human person, from conception to natural death. Human life must be valued above all material possessions.
  • Preferential option for the poor and vulnerable: Catholics believe Jesus taught that on the Day of Judgement God will ask what each person did to help the poor and needy: "Amen, I say to you, whatever you did for one of these least brothers of mine, you did for me.[60] The Catholic Church believes that through words, prayers and deeds one must show solidarity with, and compassion for, the poor. The moral test of any society is "how it treats its most vulnerable members. People are called to look at public policy decisions in terms of how they affect the poor.[61]
  • Modern Catholic social teaching is often thought to have begun with the encyclicals of Pope Leo XIII. [62]
  • Pope Leo XIII, who studied under Taparelli, published in 1891 the encyclical Rerum novarum (On the Condition of the Working Classes; lit. ; lit. "On new things"), rejecting both socialism and capitalism, while defending labor unions and private property. He stated that society should be based on cooperation and not class conflict and competition. In this document, Leo set out the Catholic Church's response to the social instability and labor conflict that had arisen in the wake of industrialization and had led to the rise of socialism. The Pope advocated that the role of the state was to promote social justice through the protection of rights, while the church must speak out on social issues to teach correct social principles and ensure class harmony. The encyclical Quadragesimo anno (On Reconstruction of the Social Order, literally "in the fortieth year") of 1931 by Pope Pius XI, encourages a living wage subsidiarity, and advocates that social justice is a personal virtue as well as an attribute of the social order, saying that society can be just only if individuals and institutions are just
  • ope John Paul II added much to the corpus of the Catholic social teaching, penning three encyclicals which focus on issues such as economics, politics, geo-political situations, ownership of the means of production, private property and the "social mortgage", and private property. The encyclicals Laborem exercens, Sollicitudo rei socialis, and Centesimus annus are just a small portion of his overall contribution to Catholic social justice. Pope John Paul II was a strong advocate of justice and human rights, and spoke forcefully for the poor. He addresses issues such as the problems that technology can present should it be misused, and admits a fear that the "progress" of the world is not true progress at all, if it should denigrate the value of the human person. He argued in Centesimus annus that private property, markets, and honest labor were the keys to alleviating the miseries of the poor and to enabling a life that can express the fullness of the human person.
  • Pope Benedict XVI's encyclical Deus caritas est ("God is Love") of 2006 claims that justice is the defining concern of the state and the central concern of politics, and not of the church, which has charity as its central social concern. It said that the laity has the specific responsibility of pursuing social justice in civil society and that the church's active role in social justice should be to inform the debate, using reason and natural law, and also by providing moral and spiritual formation for those involved in politics.
  • The official Catholic doctrine on social justice can be found in the book Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church, published in 2004 and updated in 2006 by the Pontifical Council Iustitia et Pax.

The Catechism of the Catholic Church (§§ 1928–1948) contains more detail of the church's view of social justice.

See also[edit]















References[edit]

  1. ^ Aristotle, The Politics (ca 350 BC)
  2. ^ Clark, Mary T. (2015). "Augustine on Justice," a Chapter in Augustine and Social Justice. Lexington Books. pp. 3–10. ISBN 978-1-4985-0918-3.
  3. ^ Banai, Ayelet; Ronzoni, Miriam; Schemmel, Christian (2011). Social Justice, Global Dynamics : Theoretical and Empirical Perspectives. Florence: Taylor and Francis. ISBN 978-0-203-81929-6.
  4. ^ Kitching, G. N. (2001). Seeking Social Justice Through Globalization Escaping a Nationalist Perspective. University Park, Pa: Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 3–10. ISBN 978-0-271-02377-9.
  5. ^ Hillman, Arye L. (2008). "Globalization and Social Justice". The Singapore Economic Review. 53 (2): 173–189. doi:10.1142/s0217590808002896.
  6. ^ Agartan, Kaan (2014). "Globalization and the Question of Social Justice". Sociology Compass. 8 (6): 903–915. doi:10.1111/soc4.12162.
  7. ^ El Khoury, Ann (2015). Globalization Development and Social Justice : A propositional political approach. Florence: Taylor and Francis. pp. 1–20. ISBN 978-1-317-50480-1.
  8. ^ Lawrence, Cecile & Natalie Churn (2012). Movements in Time Revolution, Social Justice, and Times of Change. Newcastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Pub. pp. xi–xv. ISBN 978-1-4438-4552-6.
  9. ^ John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971) 4, "the principles of social justice: they provide a way of assigning rights and duties in the basic institutions of society and they define the appropriate distribution of benefits and burdens of social co-operation."
  10. ^ Aiqing Zhang; Feifei Xia; Chengwei Li (2007). "The Antecedents of Help Giving in Chinese Culture: Attribution, Judgment of Responsibility, Expectation Change and the Reaction of Affect". Social Behavior and Personality. 35 (1): 135–142. doi:10.2224/sbp.2007.35.1.135.
  11. ^ Smith, Justin E. H. (2015). Nature, Human Nature, and Human Difference : Race in Early Modern Philosophy. Princeton University Press. p. 17. ISBN 978-1-4008-6631-1.
  12. ^ Trương, Thanh-Đạm (2013). Migration, Gender and Social Justice: Perspectives on Human Insecurity. Springer. pp. 3–26. ISBN 978-3-642-28012-2.
  13. ^ Teklu, Abebe Abay (2010). "We Cannot Clap with One Hand: Global Socio–Political Differences in Social Support for People with Visual Impairment". International Journal of Ethiopian Studies. 5 (1): 93–105.
  14. ^ J. Zajda, S. Majhanovich, V. Rust, Education and Social Justice, 2006, ISBN 1-4020-4721-5
  15. ^ Clark, Mary T. (2015). "Augustine on Justice," a Chapter in Augustine and Social Justice. Lexington Books. pp. 3–10. ISBN 978-1-4985-0918-3.
  16. ^ Paine, Thomas. Agrarian Justice. Printed by R. Folwell, for Benjamin Franklin Bache.
  17. ^ Luigi Taparelli, SJ, Saggio teoretico di dritto naturale appogiato sul fatto (Palermo: Antonio Muratori, 1840-43), Sections 341-364.
  18. ^ Rosmini-Serbati, The Constitution under Social Justice. trans. A. Mingardi (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2007).
  19. ^ Pérez-Garzón, Carlos Andrés (14 January 2018). "Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia". Mexican Law Review. 10 (2): 27–66. ISSN 2448-5306. Archived from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  20. ^ The Preamble of ILO Constitution
  21. ^ Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, Part II, D.
  22. ^ Plato, The Republic (ca 380BC)
  23. ^ "20th WCP: Plato's Concept of Justice: An Analysis". Archived from the original on 5 October 2016.
  24. ^ Nicomachean Ethics V.3
  25. ^ Plato, Crito (ca 380 BC)
  26. ^ T Paine, Rights of Man (1792) 197
  27. ^ Pérez-Garzón, Carlos Andrés (2018-01-14). "Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia". Mexican Law Review. 10 (2): 27–66. ISSN 2448-5306. Archived from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  28. ^ Rousseau (1774). Journal encyclopédique... [Ed. Pierre Rousseau] (in French). De l'Imprimerie du Journal.
  29. ^ L'Esprit des journaux, françois et étrangers (in French). Valade. 1784.
  30. ^ L'Episcopato ossia della Potesta di governar la chiesa. Dissertazione (in Italian). na. 1789.
  31. ^ Pérez-Garzón, Carlos Andrés (2018-01-14). "Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia". Mexican Law Review. 10 (2): 27–66. ISSN 2448-5306. Archived from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  32. ^ Pérez-Garzón, Carlos Andrés (2018-01-14). "Unveiling the Meaning of Social Justice in Colombia". Mexican Law Review. 10 (2): 27–66. ISSN 2448-5306. Archived from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  33. ^ John Allen Jr. (28 July 2009). "Ecology – The first stirring of an 'evolutionary leap' in late Jesuit's official standing?". National Catholic Reporter. Archived from the original on 24 August 2012.
  34. ^ Sandro Magister (11 January 2010). "Benedict XVI to the Diplomats: Three Levers for Lifting Up the World". chiesa, Rome. Archived from the original on 4 March 2016.
  35. ^ Sowell, Thomas (5 February 2002). The quest for cosmic justice (1st Touchstone ed.). Simon & Schuster. ISBN 0684864630.
  36. ^ John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (2005 reissue), Chapter 1, "Justice as Fairness" – 1. The Role of Justice, pp. 3–4
  37. ^ John Rawls, Political Liberalism 15 (Columbia University Press 2003)
  38. ^ John Rawls, Political Liberalism 291–92 (Columbia University Press 2003)
  39. ^ James, Nickel. "Human Rights". stanford.edu. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 February 2015.
  40. ^ Pogge, Thomas Pogge. "World Poverty and Human Rights". thomaspogge.com. Archived from the original on 19 September 2015.
  41. ^ Pogge, Thomas. "Human Rights and Just Taxation – Global Financial Transparency". Archived from the original on 10 February 2015.
  42. ^ Alison M. Jaggar1 by, ed. (2010). Thomas Pogge and His Critics (1. publ. ed.). Cambridge: Polity Press. ISBN 978-0-7456-4258-1.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: editors list (link)
  43. ^ "World Day of Social Justice, 20 February". www.un.org. Retrieved 2019-11-08.
  44. ^ "Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305" (PDF). New York: United Nations. 2006. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 August 2017.
  45. ^ "Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305" (PDF). New York: United Nations. 2006. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 August 2017.
  46. ^ "Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305" (PDF). New York: United Nations. 2006. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 August 2017.
  47. ^ "Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305" (PDF). New York: United Nations. 2006. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 August 2017.
  48. ^ "Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305" (PDF). New York: United Nations. 2006. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 August 2017.
  49. ^ "Social Justice in an Open World: The Role of the United Nations", The International Forum for Social Development, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Division for Social Policy and Development, ST/ESA/305" (PDF). New York: United Nations. 2006. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 August 2017.
  50. ^ "OHCHR | Convention on the Rights of the Child". www.ohchr.org. Retrieved 2020-12-21.
  51. ^ Sullivan, Amy (2010-06-01). "Young Evangelicals: Expanding Their Mission". Time. ISSN 0040-781X. Retrieved 2020-10-08.
  52. ^ Stott, John (2012-11-29). The Cross of Christ. InterVarsity Press. p. 185. ISBN 978-0-8308-6636-6.
  53. ^ S. R. Valentine, John Bennet & the Origins of Methodism and the Evangelical revival in England, Scarecrow Press, Lanham, 1997.
  54. ^ Carey, Brycchan. "John Wesley (1703–1791)." The British Abolitionists. Brycchan Carey, 11 July 2008. 5 October 2009. Brycchancarey.com Archived 29 January 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  55. ^ Wesley John, "Thoughts Upon Slavery," John Wesley: Holiness of Heart and Life. Charles Yrigoyen, 1996. 5 October 2009. Gbgm-umc.org Archived 16 October 2014 at the Wayback Machine
  56. ^ "Do Justice". First Free Methodist Church. Retrieved 12 June 2021.
  57. ^ The Book of Discipline of The United Methodist Church – 2012 ¶164 V, umc.org Archived 6 December 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  58. ^ The Book of Discipline of The United Methodist Church – 2008 ¶ 162 K, umc.org Archived 6 December 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  59. ^ "Seven Key Themes of Catholic Social Teaching". Archived from the original on 8 June 2007. Retrieved 29 March 2014.
  60. ^ Matthew 25:40.
  61. ^ Option for the Poor, Major themes from Catholic Social Teaching Archived 16 February 2006 at the Wayback Machine, Office for Social Justice, Archdiocese of St. Paul and Minneapolis.
  62. ^ Behr, Thomas. Social Justice and Subsidiarity: Luigi Taparelli and the Origins of Modern Catholic Social Thought (Washington DC: Catholic University of American Press, December 2019).